% LaTeX source for De Moivre's Supplementum

\documentclass{article}

\usepackage{amsmath}
\usepackage{amssymb}
\usepackage{times}

\makeatletter
\renewcommand{\section}{%
    \@startsection{section}{1}{\z@}{-3.5ex \@plus -1ex \@minus -.2ex}%
      {2.3ex \@plus .2ex}{\normalfont \Large \itshape}}
    \makeatother

\begin{document}

\setcounter{page}{75}

\begin{center}
  {\large{\textbf{DE MOIVRE}}}  \\

  \medskip

  {\large{\textbf{ON THE LAW OF NORMAL PROBABILITY}}} \\
  \ \\
  (Edited by Professor Helen M. Walker, Teachers College, Columbia \\
  University, New York City.) 
\end{center}

\noindent 

{\small Abraham de Moivre (1667-1754) left France at the revocation of 
the Edict of Nantes and spent the rest of his life in London. where he
solved problems for wealthy patrons and did private tutoring in
mathematics. He is best known for his work on trigonometry, probability.
and annuities. On November 12, 1733 he presented privately to some
friends a brief paper of seven pages entitled ``Approximatio ad Summam
Terminorum Binomii $\overline{a + b}\backslash^n$ in Seriem expansi.''
Only two copies of this are known to be extant. His own translation, with 
some additions, was included in the second edition (1738) of \textit{The 
Doctrine of Chances}, pages 235--243. 

This paper gave the first statement of the formula for the ``normal
curve,'' the first method of finding the probability of the occurrence of
an error of a given size when that error is expressed in terms of the
variability of the distribution as a unit, and the first recognition
of that value later termed the probable error. It shows, also, that
before Stirling, De Molvre had been approaching a solution of the value
of factorial $n$.} 

\medskip

{\large{\textit{A Method of approximating the Sum of the Terms of the
Binomial $\overline{a + b}\backslash^n$ expanded to a Series from whence
are deduced some practical  Rules to estimate the Degree of Assent which 
is to be given to Experiments.}}

Altho' the Solution of Problems of Chance often require that several
Terms of the Binomial $\overline{a + b}\backslash^n$ be added together, 
nevertheless in very high Powers the thing appears so laborious, and of 
so great a difficulty, that few people have undertaken that Task;  for
besides \textit{James} and \textit{Nicolas Bernoulli}, two great
Mathematicians, I know of no body that has attempted it; in which, tho'
they have shewn very great skill, and have the praise which is due to
their Industry, yet some things were farther required; for what they
have done is not so much an Approximation as the determining very wide
limits, within which they demonstrated that the Sum of the Terms was
contained. Now the Method which they have followed has been briefly
described in my \textit{Miscellanea Analytica}, which the Reader may 
consult if he pleases, unless they rather chuse, which perhaps would
he the best, to consult what they themselves have writ upon that
Subject: for my part, what made me apply myself to that Inquiry was
not out of opinion that I should excel others, in which however I might
have been forgiven; but what I did was in compliance to the desire of a
very worthy Gentleman, and good Mathematician, who encouraged me to it:
I now add some new thoughts to the former; but in order to make their
connexion the clearer, it is necessary for me to resume some few things
that have been delivered by me a pretty while ago. 

I.  It is now a dozen years or more since I had found what follows; If
the Binomial $1 + 1$ be raised to a very high Power denoted by $n$, the 
ratio which the middle Term has to the Sum of all the Terms, that is, to 
$2^n$, may he expressed by the Fraction 
$\frac{2\text{A}\times\overline{n-1}\backslash^n}{n^n\times\sqrt{n-1}}$,
wherein A represents the number of which the Hyperbolic Logarithm is  
$\frac{1}{12}-\frac{1}{360}+\frac{1}{1260}-\frac{1}{1680}$, \&c. but 
because the Quantity $\frac{\overline{n-1}\backslash^n}{n^n}$ or 
$\left.1-\frac{1}{n}\!\right|^n$ is very nearly given when $n$ is a high 
Power, which is not difficult to prove, it follows that, in an
infinite Power, that Quantity will he absolutely given, and represent
the number of which the Hyperbolic Logarithm is $-1$; from whence it
follows, that if B denotes the Number of which the Hyperbolic 
Logarithm is
$-1+\frac{1}{12}-\frac{1}{360}+\frac{1}{1260}-\frac{1}{1680}$, \&c. 
the Expression above-written will become $\frac{2\text{B}}{\sqrt{n-1}}$
or barely $\frac{2\text{B}}{\sqrt{n}}$ and that therefore if we change 
the Signs of that Series, and now suppose that B represents the Number 
of which the Hyperbolic Logarithm is 
$1-\frac{1}{12}+\frac{1}{360}-\frac{1}{1260}+\frac{1}{1680}$, \&c.
that Expression will he changed into $\frac{2}{\text{B}\sqrt{n}}$.

When I first began that inquiry, I contented myself to determine at
large the Value of B, which was done by the addition of some Terms of
the above-written Series; but as I pereciv'd that it converged but
slowly, and seeing at the same time that what I had done answered my
purpose tolerably well, I desisted from proceeding farther, till my
worthy and learned Friend Mr.\ \textit{James Stirling}, who had applied 
himself after me to that inquiry, found that the Quantity B did denote
the Square-root of the Circumference of a Circle whose Radius is Unity,
so that if that Circumference he called $c$, the Ratio of the middle
Term to the Sum of all the Terms will he expressed by 
$\frac{2}{\sqrt{nc}}$.\footnote{[Under the circumstances of De Moivre's
problem, $nc$ is equivalent to $8\sigma^2\pi$, where $\sigma$ is the 
standard deviation of the curve. This statement therefore shows that 
De Moivre knew the maximum ordinate of the curve to be 
\[\left. y_0=\frac{1}{\sigma\sqrt{2\pi}}.\right] \]}

But altho' it be not necessary to know what relation the number B may
have to the Circumference of the Circle, provided its value be attained,
either by pursuing the Logarithmic Series before mentioned, or any
other way; yet I own with pleasure that this discovery, besides that it
has saved trouble, has spread a singular Elegancy on the Solution. 

II.  I also found that the Logarithm of the Ratio which the middle Term
of a high Power has to any Term distant from it by an Interval denoted
by $l$, would he denoted by a very near approximation, (supposing 
$m=\frac{1}{2}n$) by the Quantities $\overline{m+l-\frac{1}{2}}\times
\log.\overline{m+l-1}+\overline{m-l+\frac{1}{2}}\times\overline{\log.{m-l+1}}
-2m\times\log.m+\log.\frac{m+l}{m}$.

\section*{Corollary I.}

This being admitted, I conclude, that if $m$ or $\frac{1}{2}n$ be a 
Quantity infinitely great. then the logarithm of the Ratio, which a 
Term distant from the middle by the Interval $l$, has to the middle 
Term, is $-\frac{2ll}{n}$.\footnote{[Since $n=4\sigma^2$ under the 
assumptions made here, this is equivalent to stating the formula for 
the curve as
\[ \left. y=y_0\exp^{-\frac{x^2}{2\sigma^2}}.\right] \]}

\section*{Corollary 2.}

The Number, which answers to the Hyperbolic Logarithm $-\frac{2ll}{n}$, 
being 
\[ 1-\frac{2ll}{n}+\frac{4l^4}{2nn}-\frac{8l^6}{24n^4}-\frac{32l^{10}}{120n^5}
   +\frac{64l^{12}}{720n^6},\ \text{\&c.} \]
it follows, that the Sum of the Terms intercepted between the Middle,
and that whose distance from it is denoted by $L$, will be 
$\frac{2}{\sqrt{nc}}$ into
$l-\frac{2l^3}{1\times3n}+\frac{4l^5}{2\times5nn}-\frac{8l^7}{6\times7n^3}
  +\frac{16l^9}{24\times9n^4}-\frac{32l^{11}}{120\times11n^5}$, \&c.

Let now $l$ be supposed $=s\sqrt{n}$, then the said Sum will be
expressed by the Series\newline
\qquad $\frac{2}{\sqrt{nc}}$ into
$\int-\frac{2\int^3}{3}+\frac{4\int^5}{2\times5}-\frac{8\int^7}{6\times7}
 -\frac{16\int^9}{24\times9}-32\frac{\int^{11}}{120\times11}$, 
\&c.\footnote{[The long $\int$ which De Moivre employed in this formula 
is not to be mistaken for the integral sign.]}

Moreover, if $\int$ be interpreted by $\frac{1}{2}$, then the Series 
will become $\frac{2}{\sqrt{c}}$ into
$\frac{1}{2}-\frac{1}{3\times4}+\frac{1}{2\times5\times8}
 -\frac{1}{6\times7\times16}+\frac{1}{24\times9\times32}
 +\frac{1}{120\times11\times64}$,
\&c.\ which converges so fast, that by help of no more than seven or 
eight Terms, the Sum required may he carried to six or seven places of 
Decimals: Now that Sum will he found to be 0.427812, independently from 
the common Multiplicator $\frac{2}{\sqrt{c}}$, and therefore to 
be the Tabular Logarithm\footnote{[to base 10.]} of 0.427812, which is 
$\overline{9}.6312529$, adding the Logarithm of $\frac{2}{\sqrt{c}}$ 
\textit{viz.}\ $\overline{9}.9019400$, the Sum will be $\overline{19}.5331929$, 
to which answers the number 0.341344.

\section*{Lemma}

If an Event be so dependent on Chance, as that the Probabilities of its
happening or failing be equal, and that a certain given number $n$ of
Experiments be taken to observe how often it happens and fails, and also
that $l$ be another given number, less than $\frac{1}{2}n$. then the 
Probability of its neither happening more frequently than $\frac{1}{2}n+l$ 
times, nor more rarely than $\frac{1}{2}n-l$ times, mav he found as follows. 

Let L and L be two Terms equally distant on both sides of the middle 
Term of the Binomial $\overline{1 + 1}\backslash^n$ expanded, by an 
Interval equal to $l$; let also $\int$ be the Sum of the Terms
included between L and L together with the Extreme, then the
Probability required will he rightly expressed by the Fraction
$\frac{\int}{2^n}$, which being founded on the common Principles 
of the Doctrine of Chances, requires no Demonstration in this place. 

\section*{Corollary 3.}

And therefore, if it was possible to take an infinite number of
Experiments, the Probability that an Event which has an equal number of
Chances to happen or fail, shall neither appear more frequently than in
$\frac{1}{2}n+\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$ times, nor more rarely than in 
$\frac{1}{2}n-\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$ times, will he express'd by the 
double Sum of the number exhibited in the second Corollary, that is, 
by 0.682688, and consequently the Probability of the contrary, which 
is that of happening more frequently or more rarely than in the proportion 
above assigned will he 0.317312. these two Probabilities together 
compleating Unity, which is the measure of Certainty: Now the Ratio of 
those Probabilities is in small Terms 28 to 13 very near. 

\section*{Corollary 4.}

But altho' the taking an infinite number of Experiments he not
practicable, yet the preceding Conclusions may very well he applied to
finite numbers, provided they he great, for Instance, if 3600
Experiments he taken, make $n=3600$, hence $\frac{1}{2}n$ will be $=1800$, 
and $\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$ 30, then the Probability of the Event's neither 
appearing oftner than 1830 times, nor more rarely than 1770, will he 
0.682688. 

\section*{Corollary 5.}

And therefore we may lay this down for a fundamental Maxim, that in high
Powers, the Ratio, which the Sum of the Terms included between two
Extreams distant on both sides from the middle Term by an Interval
equal to $\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$, bears to the Sum of all the Terms, 
will he rightly expres'd by the Decimal 0.682688, that is $\frac{28}{41}$ 
nearly. 

Still, it is not to be imagin'd that there is any necessity that the
number $n$ should he Immensely great; for supposing it not to reach beyond
the $900^{\textit{th}}$, Power, nay not even beyond the $100^{\textit{th}}$, 
the Rule here given will be tolerably accurate, which I have had confirmed 
by Trials. 

But it is worth whole to observe, that such a small part as is 
$\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$ in respect to $n$, and so much the less in respect
 to $n$ as $n$ increases, does very soon give the Probability
$\frac{28}{41}$ or the Odds of 28 to 13; from whence we may naturally 
he led to enquire, what are the Bounds within which the proportion of
Equality is contained; I answer, that these Bounds will he set at such a
distance from the middle Term, as will be expressed by 
$\frac{1}{4}\sqrt{2n}$ very near; so in the case above mentioned, wherein 
$n$ was supposed $=3600$, $\frac{1}{2}n+\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$ times, nor more rarely than in 
$\frac{1}{2}n-\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$ times, will he express'd by the 
double Sum of the number exhibited in the second Corollary, that is, 
by 0.682688, and consequently the Probability of the contrary, which 
is that of happening more frequently or more rarely than in the proportion 
above assigned will he 0.317312. these two Probabilities together 
compleating Unity, which is the measure of Certainty: Now the Ratio of 
those Probabilities is in small Terms 28 to 13 very near. 

\section*{Corollary 4.}

But altho' the taking an infinite number of Experiments he not
practicable, yet the preceding Conclusions may very well he applied to
finite numbers, provided they he great, for Instance, if 3600
Experiments he taken, make $n=3600$, hence $\frac{1}{2}n$ will be $=1800$, 
and $\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$ 30, then the Probability of the Event's neither 
appearing oftner than 1830 times, nor more rarely than 1770, will he 
0.682688. 

\section*{Corollary 5.}

And therefore we may lay this down for a fundamental Maxim, that in high
Powers, the Ratio, which the Sum of the Terms included between two
Extreams distant on both sides from the middle Term by an Interval
equal to $\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$, bears to the Sum of all the Terms, 
will he rightly expren'd by the Decimal 0.682688, that is $\frac{28}{41}$ 
nearly. 

Still, it is not to be imagin'd that there is any necessity that the
number $n$ should he Immensely great; for supposing it not to reach beyond
the $900^{\textit{th}}$, Power, nay not even beyond the $100^{\textit{th}}$, 
the Rule here given will be tolerably accurate, which I have had confirmed 
by Trials. 

But it is worth whole to observe, that such a small part as is 
$\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$ in respect to $n$, and so much the less in respect
 to $n$ as $n$ increases, does very soon give the Probability
$\frac{28}{41}$ or the Odds of 28 to 13; from whence we may naturally 
he led to enquire, what are the Bounds within which the proportion of
Equality is contained; I answer, that these Bounds will he set at such a
distance from the middle Term, as will be expressed by
$\frac{1}{4}\sqrt{2n}$  very near; so in the case above mentioned,
wherein $n$ was supposed $=3600$, $\frac{1}{4}\sqrt{2n}$ will be about
21.2 nearly, which in  respect to 3600, is not above $\frac{1}{169}$th
part: so that it is  an equal Chance nearly, or rather something more,
that in 3600 Experiments, in each of which an Event may as well happen
as fail, the Excess of the happenings or failings above 1800 times will
he no more than about 21. 

\section*{Corollary 6.}

If $l$ he interpreted by $\sqrt{n}$, the Series will not converge so fast 
as it did in the former case when $l$ was interpreted by 
$\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$, for here no less than 12 or 13 Terms of the Series 
will afford a tolerable approximation, and it would still require more 
Terms, according as $l$ bears a greater proportion to $\sqrt{n}$, for 
which reason I make use in this case of the Artifice of Mechanic 
Quadratures, first invented by Sir \textit{Isaac Newton}, and since 
prosecuted by Mr.\ \textit{Cotes}. Mr.\ \textit{James Stirling},
myself, and perhaps others; it consists in determining the Area of a
Curve nearly, from knowing a certain number of its Ordinates A, B, C, D,
E, F, \&c. placed at equal Intervals, the more Ordinates there are, the
more exact will the Quadrature be; but here I confine myself to four, as
being sufficient for my purpose: let us therefore suppose that the four
Ordinates are A, B, C, D, and that the Distance between the first and
last is denoted by $l$, then the Area contained between the first and the
last will be
$\frac{1\times\overline{\text{A}+\text{D}}+3\times\overline{\text{B}+\text{C}}}
      {8}\times l$; now let us take the Distances $0\sqrt{n}$,
$\frac{1}{6}\sqrt{n}$, $\frac{2}{6}\sqrt{n}$, $\frac{3}{6}\sqrt{n}$,
$\frac{4}{6}\sqrt{n}$,  $\frac{5}{6}\sqrt{n}$, $\frac{6}{6}\sqrt{n}$, of
which every one exceeds  the preceding by $\frac{1}{6}\sqrt{n}$, and of
which the last is  $\sqrt{n}$; of these let us take the four last,
\textit{viz.}\ $\frac{3}{6}\sqrt{n}$, $\frac{4}{6}\sqrt{n}$,
$\frac{5}{6}\sqrt{n}$,  $\frac{6}{6}\sqrt{n}$, then taking their
Squares, doubling each of them, dividing them all by $n$. and prefixing
to them all the Sign $-$, we shall have $-\frac{1}{2}$ $-\frac{8}{9}$,
$-\frac{1}{2}$, $-\frac{25}{18}$, $-\frac{2}{1}$, which must he look'd
upon as Hyperbolic logarithms, of which consequently the corresponding
numbers, viz. 0.60653, 0.41111, 0.24935. 0.13534 will stand for the four
Ordinates A, B, C, D.  Now having interpreted $l$ by
$\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$,  the Area will be found to be
$=0.170203\times\sqrt{n}$, the double of  which being multiplied by the
product will he 0.27160; let therefore this he added to the Area found
before, that is, to 0.682688, and the Sum 0.95428 will shew, what after
a number of Trials denoted by $n$, the Probability will he of the
Event's neither happening oftner than $\frac{1}{2}n+\sqrt{n}$ times, nor
more rarely than $\frac{1}{2}n+\sqrt{n}$, and therefore the Probability
of the contrary will be 0.04572. which shews that the Odds of the Event's
neither happening oftner nor more rarely than within the Limits assigned
are 21 to 1 nearly.  

And by the same way of reasoning, it will he found that the probability 
of the Event's neither appearing oftner $\frac{1}{2}n+\frac{3}{2}\sqrt{n}$
nor more rarely than $\frac{1}{2}n-\frac{3}{2}\sqrt{n}$ will he 0.99874, 
which will make it that the Odds in this case will he 369 to 1 nearly. 

To apply this to particular Examples, it will he necessary to estimate
the frequency of an Event's happening or failing by the Square-root of
the number which denotes how many Experiments have been, or are designed
to be taken, and this Square-root, according as at has been already
hinted at in the fourth Corollary, will he as it were the Modulus by
which we are to regulate our Estimation, and therefore suppose the
number of Experiments to be taken is 3600, and that it were required to
assign the Probability of the Event's neither happening oftner than 2850
times, nor more rarely than 1750, which two numbers may be varied at
pleasure, provided they he equally distant from the middle Sum 1800, then
make the half difference between the two numbers 1850 and 1750, that
is, in this case, $50=\int\sqrt{n}$; now having supposed $3600=n$, then 
$\sqrt{n}$ will be 60, which wdl make it that 50 will be $=60\int$, and
consequently $\int=\frac{50}{60}=\frac{5}{6}$, and therefore if we take the 
proportion, which in an infinite power, the double Sum of the Terms 
corresponding to the Interval $\frac{5}{6}\sqrt{n}$, bears to the Sum of 
all the Terms, we shall have the Probability required exceeding near. 

\section*{Lemma 2.}

In any Power $\overline{a + b}\backslash^n$ expanded. the greatest Term 
is that in which the Indices of the Powers of $a$ and $b$. have the same 
proportion to one another as the Quantities themselves $a$ and $b$; thus 
taking the $10^{\textit{th}}$ Power of $a+b$, which is
$a^{10}+10a^9b+45a^8b^2+120a^7b^3+210a^6b^4+252a^5b^5+210a^4b^6+120a^3b^7
 +45a^2b^8+10ab^9+b^{10}$ 
and supposing that the proportion of $a$ to $b$ is as 3 to 2, then the Term
$210a^6b^4$ will be the greatest, by reason that the Indices of the Powers
of $a$ and $b$, which are in that Term, are in the proportion of 3 to 2;
but supposing the proportion of $a$ to $b$ had been as 4 to 1, then the Term
$45a^8b^2$ had been the greaust 

\section*{Lemma 3.}

If an Event so depends on Chance, as that the Probabilities of its
happening or failing be in any assigned proportion, such as may he
supposed of $a$ to $b$, and a certain number of Experiments be designed
to be taken, in order to observe how often the Event will happen or
fail; then the Probability that it shall neither happen more frequently
than so many times as are denoted by $\frac{an}{a+b}+l$, nor more
rarely than so many times as are denoted by $\frac{an}{a+b}-l$
will be found as follows: 

Let L and R be equally distant by the Interval $l$ from the greatest
Term; let also S be the Sum of the Terms included between L and R,
together with those Extreams, then the Probability required will be 
rightly expressed by $\frac{\text{S}}{\overline{a+b}\backslash^n}$.

\section*{Corollary 8.\footnote{[Numbered as in the original. There
is no corollary 7 in the text.]}}

The Ratio which, in an infinite Power denoted by $n$. the greatest Term
bears to the Sum of all the rest, will be rightly expressed by 
the Fraction $\frac{a+b}{\sqrt{abnc}}$, wherein $c$ denotes, as before, 
the Circumference of a Circle for a Radius equal to Unity. 

\section*{Corollary 9.}

If, in an infinite Power. any Term be distant from the Greatest 
by the Interval $l$, then the hyperbolic logarithm of the Ratio
which that Term bears to that Greatest will be expressed by the 
Fraction $-\frac{\overline{a+b}^2}{2abn}\times ll$; provided 
the Ratio of $l$ to $n$ be not a finite Ratio, but such a one 
as may he conceived between any given number $p$ and $\sqrt{n}$, 
so that $l$ be expressible by $p\sqrt{n}$, in which case the two 
Terms L and R will be equal. 

\section*{Corollary 10.}

If the Probabilities of happening and failing be in any given Ratio of
unequality, the Problems relating to the Sum of the Terms of the
Binomial $\overline{a+b}\backslash^n$ will be solved with the same 
facility as those in which the Probabilities of happening and failing 
are in a Ratio of Equality. 

From what has been said, it follows, that Chance very little disturbs
the Events which in their natural Institution were designed to happen or
fail, according to some determinate law; for if in order to help our
conception, we imagine a round piece of Metal, with two polished
opposite faces, differing in nothing but their colour, whereofore may be
supposed to be white, and the other black; it is plain that we may say,
that this piece may with equal facility exhibit a white or black face,
and we may even suppose that it was framed with that particular view of
shewing sometimes one face, sometimes the other, and that consequently
If it be tossed up Chance shall decide the appearance; but we have seen
in our \textsc{lxxxvii}$^{\text{th}}$ Problem, that altho' Chance may
produce an inequality of appearance. and still a greater inequality
according to the length of time in which it may exert itself, still the
appearances, either one way or the other, will perpetually tend to a
proportion of Equality; but besides we have seen in the present Problem,
that In a great number of Experiments, such as 3600, it would be the
Odds of above 2 to 1, that one of the Faces, suppose the white, shall
not appear more frequently than 1830 times, nor more rarely than 1770,
or in other Terms, that it shall not be above or under the perfect 
Equality by more than $\frac{1}{120}$ part of the whole number of
appearances; and by the same Rule, that if the number of Trials had been
14400 instead of 3600, then still it would be above the Odds of 2 to 1,
that the appearances either one way or other would not deviate from
perfect Equality by more than $\frac{1}{260}$ part of the whole, but in 
1000000 Trials it would be the Odds of above 2 to 1, that the deviation
from perfect Equality would not he more than by $\frac{1}{2000}$ part of
the whole. But the Odds would increase at a prodigious rate, if instead
of taking such narrow limits on both sides the Term of Equality, as are
represented by $\frac{1}{2}\sqrt{n}$, we double those Limits or triple
them; for in the first case the Odds would become 21 to 1, and in the
second 369 to 1, and still he vastly greater if we were to quadruple
them, and at last be infinitely great; and yet whether we double, triple
or quadruple them, \&c. the Extension of those Limits will bear but an
inconsiderable proportion to the whole, and none at all, if the whole be
infinite, of which the reason will easily be perceived by
Mathematicians, who know, that the Square-root of any Power bears so
much a less proportion to that Power, as the Index of it is great. 

And what we have said is also applicable to a Ratio of Inequality, as
appears from our $9^{\text{th}}$ Corollary.  And thus in all cases it
will he found, that altho' Chance produces irregularities, still the
Odds will be infinitely great, that in process of Time, those
Irregularities will bear no proportion to the recurrency of that Order
which naturally results from original Design. 

\end{document}

%